ment. In this speech he attempts to persuade Alexandrian citizens to reform their riotous conduct before more serious consequences befall them, noting that a recent confrontation between themselves and the prefect of Egypt (L. Peducaeus Colonus) and his forces had attracted the interest of the Roman authorities.2 Although the prefect had tried to defuse the situation some trouble-makers, described as 'headstrong and unruly spirits who purposely aimed at complete overthrow and utter chaos', brought 'a taste of warfare' on those present, #72. In citing this incident Dio hopes to convince his audience that the confrontation flowed inexorably from the disorderliness which ruled their lives. It was epitomised by their unruly conduct in the theatre (#73-74).3 They had been played upon by Cynics who deliberately incited thoughtless people to deride philosophers, #10. The problems were also linked to the philosophers' abdication of their roles in politeia, creating a gap which orators and poets attempted to fill. In the end none of these groups — which included
the many sophists — overcame the problem with Rome that was ag-
Dio as Alexandria's counsellor and savior
The initial discussion of all these groups occurs in #8-11 within the lengthy introduction, #1-29. There Dio seeks to establish his own credentials as counselor and saviour of Alexandria through his use of comparison with philosophers, sophists, orators and poets. J. L. Moles defines 'counsellor' (σύμβουλος) as 'the typical figure of the external adviser interfering from a higher plane'.5 Dio may appear in the garb of a philosopher (traditionally 'clad in a mean cloak') but, as he tells his audience, he has been appointed to the task of addressing the Alexandrians 'by the will of some deity', #22,12. The 'deity' in question is Vespasian, to whom Alexandria had recently granted the traditional divine honours immediately on his accession to the Principate.6 It would seem that Dio came with the knowledge and blessing of Vespasian, as his ambassador.
Dio hoped to heal a rift between the emperor and the Alexandrians. The city's fortunes, robust under Nero, had been sharply reversed under Vespasian even though it was here that the legions first recognised his claim to the Principate in A.D. 69. Cassius Dio records the city's disappointment at receiving as a reward for its acceptance of his claim only a heavier tax burden.
4On the use here of politeia as 'the way of life of the state' see J. Bordes, Politeia dans la pensee grecque jusqu'a Aristote (Paris: "Belle Lettres", 1982), p. 116. For an analysis of the structure of the oration see Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 40, with the lengthy preface #1-19, behaviour at public entertainment #20-40, citharody and chariot racing discussed together #41-46, and then separately #46-74, 74-95, and the epilogue #95-101, which brings together introductory themes and relates them to their position with the emperor and their general attitudes to politeia, #97-100.
5Moles sees Dio in this role not only in Or. 32 but also in the speech at Rhodes, Or. 31, and that delivered to his native city, Prusa, Or. 46. He argues that this oration 'foreshadows' Dio's role in 'philosopho-political symbouleutics', 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 93. Whether 'foreshadows' is the best term is debatable, for Dio seems at home in this role in the orations of this period. On synkrisis see #39 and C. Forbes, 'Comparison, Selfpraise and Irony: Paul's Boasting and Conventions of Hellenistic Rhetoric', NTS 32 (1986), 2-8 for Dio's use of this term.
6Dio says he comes as Hermes at the behest of Zeus, #21. The latter was identified with a reigning emperor; Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, pp. 44 and 174, n. 83. See also A. Henrichs, 'Vespasian's Visit to Alexandria', ZPE 3(1968),58-80, for the Ptolemaic concept of the emperor as the 'living image of Zeus' and the Alexandrians granting divine descent to Vespasian.
42
Their dashed hopes turned to mocking and questioning of his ability to rule, and soon to open and 'foolhardy' demonstrations at which they abused 'the good nature of the emperor'.7 It was 'that impudent licence which is always working to their detriment' with which the Alexandrians abused the emperor, Cassius Dio notes;8 Suetonius added that they called him a 'fishmonger'.9
The conclusion of the oration holds out the possibility of an imperial visit, and even benefactions, if the Alexandrians could prove themselves by their restraint 'worthy of his favour and trust', #95. Dio aims then to convince the citizens that they must heed him, for 'in plain terms and without guile [he] speaks his mind with frankness', #11: he is their 'counsellor and saviour',10 concerned for the well-being of his audience. Two factors must be constantly before us as we evaluate Dio and his discussion of, and synkrisis with, philosophers, orators, poets and sophists. First, his speech must be weighed in the light of his overriding ambition to succeed in this difficult imperial mission. Second, any assessment of Dio's role, especially in relation to philosophers and sophists, must be made in the light of recent events in Rome and Dio's response to them.
In A.D. 71 Vespasian had expelled all philosophers from Rome with the exception of the noted Musonius Rufus.11 The Cynics he singled out for special
7Cassius Dio, Roman History, LXV, 8: 'Six obols more you demand of us', they taunted and in a crowded assembly they all shouted in chorus at Vespasian's son, Titus, 'We forgive him;for he knows not how to play the Caesar.'
8Vespasian was only dissuaded from taking retaliatory action on 'the obols' issue by his son, Titus. Cassius Dio also notes, 'But Vespasian soon ceased to notice them.' The text seems to suggest that matters of higher priority in Rome took precedence in Vespasian's thinking, especially as his imperial claims had not yet been finally secured. The reference to 'soon restoring order to Egypt' may point to further troubles arising out of the spurning of Vespasian, Roman History, LXV, 8.
9Cassius Dio, Vespasian, 19.2. 'The Alexandrians persisted in calling him Cybiosacten, the surname of one of their kings who was scandalously stingy.' Cybiosacten is a transliteration of the Greek κυβιοσάκτης, a dealer in square pieces of salt fish, LCL, vol. II, p. 312. On the belligerence of the Alexandrians even towards royals, see also Dio Chrysostom, Or. 32.22.
10Dio says at the beginning of his oration that Greeks have the heritage of παιδεία and λόγος, which makes them σωτῆρες τῶν πόλεων, #3. On the designation of the prefect as 'saviour of Egypt' and 'saviour' see, e.g. P.Fouad 26 (A.D. 157-59), lines 26, 49-50; of the emperor as 'saviour of the whole human race' see Select Papyri, vol II, no. 211 (A.D. 19), lines 38-40, and on the sestertius issued at Rome by Vespasian in A.D. 71 as 'liberator' or 'saviour' of Rome from slavery see A. Watson, 'Vespasian: Adsertor Libertatis Publicae', CR (n.s.) 23 (1973), 127-28.
11On the expulsion see Cassius Dio, Roman History, LXV, 13. On the disappointment of philosophers with Vespasian as emperor and their discussion of the restoration of the republic see Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 83, n. 41 and Desideri, Dione di Prusa, ch. 2, section 1.
43
mention, perhaps because he, like Seneca, found them to be 'rebellious and fractious persons, over-riding kings and officials and those responsible for the conduct of public affairs'.12 They taught many doctrines 'inappropriate to the times' and publicly criticised the relationship of Vespasian's son, Titus, with Berenice.13 Dio's own lost work attacked philosophers in general and Stoics and Cynics in particular.14 He is said to have argued that philosophers should 'be expelled from every land and sea in the belief that they are Messengers of Death to state and civil organisations alike'.15 His comments on the threat of retaliatory measures may therefore be linked with Cynic activity in Alexandria,16 and his censure of the philosophers there must be coloured to some extent by recent events in the capital, all the more so if he comes as an imperial messenger. Moles calls Dio's stance in A.D. 71 'a pose of expediency in a moment of crisis'. However, there seems to be a consistency in attitude on the part of Dio from the time of the expulsion of philosophers from Rome to the delivery of this oration. The Rhodian discourse is dated by Jones prior to the Alexandrian discourse but after the expulsion of the philosophers. Dio's praise of the famous philosopher Musonius Rufus does not deny his consistency. This Stoic philosopher was the only one not expelled by Vespasian in the initial election in A.D. 71, Or. 31.122. According to Fronto, Dio was a pupil of Musonius Rufus.17 These two factors will be considered as we examine his discussion of philosophers, especially with respect to (1) their role in politeia, and (2) those who attempted to stand in their place in politeia, namely orators, sophists and poets.
Philosophers as former leaders in politeia
In apportioning blame for the present instability in Alexandria, Dio tells his audience that they may not have been wholly culpable, #8. Earlier Dio sug-
12Seneca, Ep. Mor. 73.
13Cassius Dio, Roman History, LXV, 15. For discussion see R. H. Dudley, A History of Cynicism from Diogenes to the 6th Century A.D. (London: Methuen, 1937), ch. 7.
14On his κατὰ τῶν φιλοσόφων, no longer extant, see Synesius, Dio Chrysostom, LCL, vol. V, p. 373, and Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 85-87, for discussion. Jones, 'The Date of Dio of Prusa's Alexandrian Oration', 305, sees a connection between this lost work and Or. 32 on Dio's attitude to philosophers.
15Cited in Dio Chrysostom, LCL, vol. V, p. 373.
16Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 44.
17Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 94. For the discussion of Dio's Πρὸς Μουσώνιον, which is no longer extant, see Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 82-83 and 85-88, and for the dating of Or. 31, see Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 133.
44
gested the problem could have been avoided if the Alexandrians had made use of their heritage, namely 'education and rhetoric' (παιδεία καὶ λόγος). The blessings bestowed on those who have participated in them are that they make 'good men' (ἄνδρες ἀγαθοί) and 'saviours of the cities' (σωτῆρες τῶν πόλεων). The present emperor is devoted to them, and they are the remedy of the gods for κακία, #60, 61. Paideia is meant to produce the opposite of evil, i.e., virtue. The latter cannot flourish because the former does. Dio lists the vices as 'stupid contention', 'unbridled ambition', 'vain grief, 'senseless joy', 'raillery' and 'extravagance', #5 and the traditional virtues, #5,37,47,55,95,96. He tells them later that their conduct negates these blessings and could make them ἀπαίδευτος, #62. Responsibility rests with the one who 'wears the name philosopher'.18 Dio divides the philosophers into two groups.19 There are some 'who do not appear in public' at all because they despair of ever effecting an improvement in 'the masses'.20 Thus they have 'quit the field and are silent' out of concern for their dignity, #19. They now serve no more purpose in politeia than shadow boxers, the scourge of the wrestling schools and gymnasia who view 'with suspicion the sun's heat and the blows', for they have abdicated their traditional role as admonishers of the citizens, #20. Dio reiterates this charge when he later states, 'In my opening remarks also I laid blame for this [disorder] upon the philosophers who will not appear before the people or even deign to converse with you', #20.
The second group21 wish to exercise their voices in 'what we call lecture-halls'.22 Since for Dio the theatre represents 'the organ of hearing of the people', his comment placing the philosophers in lecture-halls rather
18The use of the phrase 'so-called' by Dio is his way of indicating that the term is inappropriate to those who use it of themselves because of their unprofessional conduct, e.g., Or. 13.11, 34.3, noted by Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 91, and for further evidence Or. 77/8.34-35, cf. Or. 49.3.
19Cf. Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 172, n. 22.
20πλῆθος and πολλοί are used in the same sentence in #48. Moles argues that, in Dio, οἱ πολλοί are nearly always mistaken about everything. In Or. 32 the context demands that πλῆθος means the people in the theatre, #11,20, as it does also in #8, and LCL's translation of εἰς πλῆθος as 'in public' could convey the wrong impression that Dio is stating that they do not go out into the city. His charge is that they will not address the citizens in the theatre, Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 89.
21#97-98. Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 37, suggests (1) that Dio must be referring in part to members of the Museum and (2) that 'the wise Theophilus', who resided in the city and may have been a member of it, never addressed it.
22See n. 8 above. Dio would seem to imply that the philosophers might call it a lecture-hall, but it is not really that because they are not teaching the right people. Their right place is in the theatre among the δῆμος.
45
than in the theatre is critical. He himself addressed the Alexandrian crowd in the theatre, and in so doing fulfilled the traditional role of the philosophers. Contemporary philosophers, however, have now secured an alliance with other audiences, and they and their lecture-hall audience mutually neglect any obligations in the assembly. The philosophers have not simply surrendered their traditional role, but have adopted many of the sophists' activities. Dio's invective at this point would have aimed to humiliate the Alexandrian philosophers who prided themselves that they were not like the sophists.
Further distinctions are drawn between two types of philosophers: a
'bad' philosopher lacks severity, for 'severity of speech is by nature salutary',23 while a 'good' one uses 'persuasion and reason' (πειθὸς καὶ λόγος) 'to calm and soften the soul'. They should be the 'saviours and guardians' of all who can be saved, but a dearth exists, for men prefer wealth and power to importance in the polis. While 'magistrates, laws and jurymen' have the function of 'cautery and the knife' for the drastic treatment of vice, the philosopher's task resembles 'dieting and drugs'. This treatment is preferable, but in Alexandria they have neglected their practice of it. The bad philosopher then is one who fails to assist in politeia or serve as the 'saviour and guardian' through the exercise of his powers of persuasion and reason, #18-19. The good philosopher will do so in spite of abuse, rebuttal and derision from the crowd. Dio says he is empathetic to the philosophers' problem of the awesome and intimidating nature of the Alexandrian crowd. He tells them it is not easy to endure their uproar, #20. He uses a variety of methods to secure and retain the attention of the crowd. It reflects his skill that he uses praise, he evokes pathos for himself and attributes the ensuing silence to the supernatural, #2,29,30,33.
The Cynic philosophers of Alexandria are singled out for special condemnation. He tolerates their fundamental beliefs, for 'they comprise practically nothing spurious or ignoble', #9, but he condemns their eccentricity because of the studiously shameless begging which has brought ridicule upon philosophers in general.24 In this regard he resembles Epictetus, who endorsed the ideal Cynic philosopher as a type of perfect wise man, but de-
23τὸ δὲ τοῦ λόγου πικρὸν σῴζειν, lit. 'the sharpness of speech produces the saving [of the people]', #18. LCL has not translated δῆμος to show a continuation of thought within the same paragraph. On the role of the philosopher to censure and rebuke the audience see Or. 33.10, 36.38.
24The construction ἀλλὰ χρείων τροφῆς expresses his disgust; LCL translates "yet who
must make a living — still these Cynics (οὗτοι δέ)'. It would seem Dio is holding them to ridicule before the crowd, for they too have to make 'a livelihood'.
46
nounced the contemporary Cynic philosophers for their begging with a citation from Homer: 'dogs of the table, guards at the gate'.25
In Or. 32 comments are related to the majority of Alexandrian Cynics26 and expose their shortcomings in two areas. Firstly, Dio will be recognised as a man who 'in plain terms and without guile speaks his mind with frankness'; thus he embodies the virtues of the prototypical wise man. His passing reference to, and his basic agreement with, this fundamental Cynic ideal, prepares the way for his own self-praise, #11,8.27
Secondly, he explains that Cynic begging and constant railing against other philosophers have exacted a high price, because Alexandrians have come to despise all philosophers. The Cynics had betrayed a profession which served to knock insolence out of the people, rather than increase it as they themselves had done. The tragic consequence of this 'arrogance', #9, was the heavy-handed Roman intervention, #71.
The evaluation of the traditional role of the Alexandrian philosopher raises a number of points. Dio refers to the traditional and highly significant role of philosophers in politeia and adopts a stance towards their behavior which is very much in harmony with that of Rome; Vespasian had evicted them because of their opposition to his rule. That this policy would have met with Dio's approval seems clear given his view of the philosopher described in this oration.28 Dio's charge hits at the Alexandrian philosophers' failure to lead the citizens of their great city, and not at their role as critics of the em-
25Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 94, and Epictetus, III.22.80 for the Homeric citation, Iliad, XXII.69.
26Contra Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 94.
27On Dio's relationship to Cynic philosophy and what C. P. Jones calls the modern invention of his conversion to Cynicism during his exile at the end of the century, see Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, pp. vi, 49 and 175, n. 35. There Jones traces the conversion thesis of 1887 to its adoption by R. Hoistad, Cynic Hero and Cynic King (Uppsala: Bloms, 1948). Jones notes that it has never received universal endorsement although it was adopted by the LCL editors. Dudley, A History of Cynicism, p. 156, in his desire to promote the idea of Dio the Cynic, makes no reference to the negative comments in the Alexandrian oration. B. F. Harris, 'Dio of Prusa', notes a recent tendency wrongly to include Dio 'loosely' among the Cynics. Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 79 and 94, feels that Dio's Cynicism became more pronounced during his exile, but that comment must be seen in the light of his view of Dio's pragmatism and not as support for a Cynic period. Desideri, Dione di Prusa, pp. 537-47, clearly shows that modern scholars made him into a Cynic in order to help in the reconstruction of a history of development of Cynicism. He suggests that there were 'elements of Cynic thinking', but this certainly did not make him into a 'classical' Cynic.
28On Dio's call for submission to Roman authority see #95. In Or. 32, 'Dio's sympathies are with Rome. The Romans are the benevolent guardians of the city, the Alexandrians are unruly "children".' Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 127.
47
peror's performance.29 Just as Vespasian dealt harshly with the Cynics in Rome, so too Dio has censured their behaviour in Alexandria because of the denigration of the philosopher's role as saviour and guardian of the city. Dio's description of the role of the ideal philosopher in politeia is noted in other orations such as Or. 36.38, where they 'share in πολιτεία'. In the first Tarsian discourse Dio commended the work of Athenodorus, the Stoic philosopher and former tutor of Augustus, who was sent to reform that city and was subsequently appointed governor. Also, Philostratus tells us that Dio himself was noted as one who 'very often rebuked cities…like one who restrains an unruly
horse with the bridle rather than the whip'.30 As a direct result of this, their leadership role has fallen to others.
Orators, poets and sophists as present leaders in politeia
Dio's concern extends beyond the philosophers' activities and motivations to an interest in what happens when they themselves 'quit the field and are silent'. In Alexandria, to nobody's credit, the orators and poets filled the vacuum. There was a heavy demand for forensic orators because there had sprung up 'a multitude of quarrels and lawsuits, harsh cries, tongues that are mischievous and unrestrained, accusers, calumnies, writs, a horde of professional pleaders', #19.31
In addition to the forensic orators, two other groups described as 'those
29Moles, however, regards the Rhodian Oration as an 'elegant recantation (at least with regard to Musonius)'. He argues that Πρὸς Μουσώνιον was a debate milder than Dio's work κατὰ τῶν φιλοσόφων. In 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 86-87, Moles suggests that Dio's position at that time was one of living with 'common notions' rather than philosophy by which issues of political life would be removed from the province of Stoic, Cynic and all philosophers. It is possible to argue that there was a continuity in the stance taken by Dio in Rome and Alexandria, namely the role of the philosopher within the δῆμος. This role is certainly present in Or. 32. For a former pupil to be critical of his teachers is not unheard of, as Moles notes. We are not at all certain that Πρὸς Μουσώνιον, now lost, was highly critical. On πρός and κατά see Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 85, n. 51. What is clear is that Vespasian did not ban Musonius Rufus from Rome when he banned all others. Therefore any encomium of Musonius such as we have in the Rhodian Oration, delivered prior to the Alexandrian, shows no conflict with the emperor's attitude to this distinguished philosopher, nor does the evidence force us to posit such a hypothesis of 'elegant recantation'.
30Or. 33.48, LCL, vol. III, pp. 318-19, n. 1. Lives of the Sophists, 487. See Or. 49 for Dio's discussion of the importance of philosophers in the administration of the affairs of state.
31For quarrels Dio uses 'strife' (ἔρις), and combines this elsewhere with civil strife, Or. 17.10, 19.8, 34.44, 36.22; enmity, 48.6, and jealousy (φιλόνικος), 39.8, 48.6, 53.2; and greed (φθόνος), 77/8.39.
48
who are educated' (πεπαιδευμένοι) emerged in the absence of the philosophers. One group, 'those who declaim speeches for display' (oἱ μὲν ἐπιδεικτικοὺς λόγους κτλ.) are identified in the same paragraph as orators. The others are the poets, #10.
Dio tells the Alexandrians there is nothing terribly shocking in what an orator does, even though in his declamations he shows he is 'unlearned'.32 However, he takes exception when orators disguise themselves as philosophers for 'deceitful' motives,33 performing only for personal gain and 'reputation'.
Two important observations about these deliberative orators emerge from Dio's comments. Firstly, we have seen that the rhetorician filled a leadership role in politeia, normally associated with the Second Sophistic, and obviously already well established in Alexandria. This is corroborated by the role expected of Nicetes of Smyrna, a first-century sophist of Nero's reign who was skilled in both forensic, rhetoric and declamation. He should have addressed the citizens of Smyrna regularly, for they had bestowed upon him their highest honours. Thus when he failed to do so on a regular basis, they accused him of cowardice.34
Secondly, Dio accuses the orators of being 'deceitful', for they feign an interest in the welfare of the citizens, but their real concern is for 'gain and glory'. The accusation that orators were primarily interested in their own pecuniary advantage goes back to the first sophist, Protagoras, who charged fees for lectures.35 This is a charge that the critics of the sophists would find easy to verify, as the evidence of Neilus against Didymus clearly shows.36 Dio, in linking money and reputation, may be suggesting that a substantial fee was
32LCL translates the phrase as 'and stupid to boot', highlighting καὶ τούτους, which precedes ἀμαθής. The latter word means 'stupid' or 'unlearned' or perhaps in this context 'not calculated to educate'. Dio believes that declaiming on a particular event from the past in the way they do will not bring about the reformation of the Alexandrians.
33δεινός means either 'shocking', preferred by LCL, or possibly 'deceitful'. Dio notes elsewhere that others have come before the Alexandrians praising them for being σοφός τε καὶ δεινός, 'both wise and clever', #2. There Dio uses a non-pejorative meaning, but here the term is pejorative. Dio brings this out clearly, for he has just stated that while there is nothing shocking in producing unlearned declamations, there is everything wrong when orators pose as philosophers for gain and glory.
34Philostratus, Lives of the Sophists, 511-12.
35On the issue of fees see Kerferd, The Sophistic Movement (Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1981), pp. 26-28, and Philostratus' defence of the system in his discussion of Protagoras to the effect that one only values what is paid for and therefore it was not a practice to be despised, Lives of the Sophists, 494.
36P.Oxy. 2190, lines 30-31, a charge he levels at them.
49
paid to an orator declaiming in the theatre. Alternatively, he could mean that an appearance in the theatre was a form of free advertising by which pupils were attracted to one's school. His words could in some cases mean both, for one established a reputation by appearing there before a large crowd. Philostratus remarks that the path to fame was to present a long oration about one's own renown, for 'this style of speech is likely to win favour for sophists in their public declamations'.37 Reputation could attract great honours, and there were very famous sophists upon whom such were bestowed as Philostratus records.38 Dio conceives of the rhetor's mission as addressing the public in place of the philosophers in order to improve the conduct of the body politic. Not only does he indict the philosophers for failing in this responsibility to the citizens, but he condemns the orators who do appear, because they are simply self-seeking.
The poets, as 'those who are educated' (πεπαιδευμένοι) also had a right to
centre-stage in politeia. Dio had already alluded to their role in Athens where they had confronted not only the individual citizens for misdemeanours, but also the city-state. He counted this to their credit, and regrets that Alexandria had neither this tradition nor the poets 'to reprove you in all friendliness and reveal the weaknesses of your city', #6-7.39 He laments that Alexandria, 'the second Athens', has not followed the Athenian precedent. They have no chorus, no poets, nor anyone else to admonish them, #7. He reminds them that originally poets were regarded as being possessed by the Muses when they spoke their messages from the gods, but the more recent poets speak of their own wisdom in the assembly. 'Uninitiated addressing uninitiated', he concludes. The poets who have stood before the Alexandrians have adjusted their presentation to suit the foibles of the audience as they 'sing' their poems, Or. 36.35-38.
Dio directs his hostility not at the poets' profession per se but at the fact that the Alexandrian poets, like the orators, practice deception. They come in the guise of philosophers for their own financial and personal advancement rather than for the improvement of the citizens. He illustrates both groups' lack of professional integrity by revisiting the medical analogy we saw above: a physician would not disregard the treatment and ultimate care of his patient by bringing useless gifts of flowers and perfumes or even harmful gifts
37That this sophist, Polemo, did not do so when he came to Athens was a sign of his arrogance, for 'he conversed with cities as his inferiors, Emperors as not his superiors, and the gods as his equals', Lives of the Sophists, 535.
38For the imperial honours heaped on Polemo of Laodicea and the city honours bestowed on Nicetes see Lives of the Sophists, 512, 532-33.
39On the use of this role in Old Comedy see Horace, Satires, 1.4.1-5.
50
such as courtesans, #10. Yet orators and poets have done precisely this to the
Alexandrians.
Generalisations are tempered with the ironical observation that a few have displayed frankness before the Alexandrian audience. Yet even those have been found wanting. They have merely uttered 'a phrase or two' and, after berating rather than enlightening the audience, they have fled from the theatre lest they should be expelled from the city, #11.
Having denounced those motivated by false motives and the few who panicked and fled, Dio then spells out the qualifications of the person whom Alexandria really needs.
But to find a man who in plain terms, and without guile speaks his mind with frankness, and neither for the sake of reputation nor for gain makes false pretension, but out of good will and concern for his fellow-men stands ready, if need be, to submit to ridicule, and the disorder and uproar of the mob — to find such a man is not easy, but rather the good fortune of a very lucky city, so great is the dearth of noble, independent souls. (#11)
The Alexandrians, however, are fortunate, for Dio, unlike 'the abundance of flatterers, impostors and sophists', offers himself as that fearless, noble and independent soul.40
Dio's self-promotion as the ideal wise leader and adviser at this point is the culmination of his synkrisis with orators and poets, but it is by no means the end of it, for he has another criticism of them. He returns to the theme in #39 where he asserts that his aim is not 'to compare' himself (παραβάλλειν) with those 'who habitually sing such strains, whether orators or poets'.41 While denying that he wishes to engage in synkrisis with poets and orators, he very skilfully does exactly that by alluding to the superiority of the theme he treats. They praise the Alexandrians by praising their environs: Dio argues that only praise of men's virtue has value, and then spells out three of the traditional four cardinal virtues and a host of subsidiary ones, #39b-
40'Flatterer' (κόλαξ), 'cheat' (γόης). LCL translates 'toadies and sophists'. On the meaning of the term 'sophist' in Dio and the linking of the above terms with sophists see Demosthenes, De Corona, 276, Plato, Symposium, 203d and pp. 55-58. On Philo's use see pp. 88-91.
41On Dio's use of παραβολή as a synonym for σύγκρισις see Forbes, 'Comparison, Selfpraise and Irony', 4-5, and his discussion of #39 where he suggests Dio is denying the charge of being a flatterer. Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 40, identifies #35-36 as a miniature encomium and argues that Dio first praises the citizens by commending the city and then jolts them by saying he is not praising them. It would seem that Dio is not answering the charge of 'flattery', contra Forbes, for having used the actual word ἐγκώμιον in #37, he is at pains to say he does not want the audience to engage in a synkrisis between himself and these others.
51
40.42 The gods provide a remedy for the city's ills 'education and reason' (παιδεία καὶ λόγος), #16 (cf. #3). Since those who should have administered the medicine failed because they were preoccupied with money and reputation, Dio must serve in their place to ensure that by constant application of the cure of the gods, the Alexandrians can come at last to 'a healthy, happy end', #16. He thus establishes his credentials before the Alexandrians by clearly demonstrating the inadequacy of those who have claimed for themselves leadership roles in the city, namely sophists and poets. He has done so through the skilful use of synkrisis and finally through invoking his appointment by a god at whose bidding he speaks. Dio tells them it is the will of a certain god that he should speak to them. He also declares that this god must not only be thought to speak in dreams or through young boys, but 'if one hears words of wisdom, we must believe that they too were sent by god', #12-1443
He also refers to those involved in philosophy and rhetoric in his denunciation of citharody,44 asserting that 'the people of Alexandria are carried away by song as no other people are, and that if they hear the music of the lyre, however bad, they lose their senses', #65.45 This mania had a considerable effect on philosophers, including Cynics, as well as orators and sophists, because they adjusted their style to this whim of the Alexandrians, #68.
Dio sees a correlation between, on the one hand, the singing mania of the citizens and their intellectual leaders, and on the other, the subsequent social disorder. He may have drawn this connection from Plato who, in his Republic, proposed to ban new music styles because he felt that they promoted social and political unrest.46 'Singing' is to Dio's mind a 'disease' which infects not only orators but also philosophers, #68. Some suggest that his claim to being a poor singer contains a sarcastic allusion to declaimers, #22, and that the 'singing' refers to a form of chanting, or even to the delivery of the peroration of a
42Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 40, suggests that Dio has artfully constructed this encomium. There is a similarity between Dio at this point and Paul in 2 Cor. 10.12; see pp. 232-34. For a discussion of Philo's traditional virtues see my treatment of this, pp. 83-87.
43For the identification of this god with Serapis and the famous centre at Alexandria see LCL, vol. III, p. 183, n. 3. For some of the added details of its founding by Ptolemy III and its role in the confirmation of Vespasian's imperial claim see Henrichs, 'Vespasian's Visit to Alexandria', 54-65. Although Dio does not identify the god by name, it must be Serapis, for the reference reads 'most in honour and to you especially does he display his power through almost daily oracles and dreams', #12.
44The cithara was a portable harp often used to accomany singing.
45E. K. Borthwick, 'Dio Chrysostom on the Mob at Alexandria', CR 22 (1972), 1. Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, pp. 41-42.
46Republic, 424c.
52
speech in a sing-song fashion. Philostratus suggests that the sophists spoke in a sing-song voice suited to the metrical rhythms of the Asianists, especially in the peroration where the use of this term was meant to sway the audience or the jury.47 This last suggestion may explain Dio's slur that if you passed a courtroom, you could not easily decide whether you heard a drinking party or a trial. Likewise if there was a sophist's lecture room in the neighbourhood, you would not know that a lecture was in progress. Quintilian also complains that this new trend Outrages the dignity of the courts with noises such as are dear to the Lycians and Carians', a reference to the Asianists' style.48 Earlier Dio indicates that Alexandria was not alone in this, for he has heard philosophers 'singing' elsewhere, but singing Cynics are an Alexandrian first, #62.49
These comments provide clear evidence of a capitulation to audience demands, and, more importantly, of philosophers necessarily responding to innovation by orators and sophists. The rebuke by Isaeus to his student Dionysius of Miletus, 'Young man from Ionia, I did not train you to sing', seems to have availed nothing. Dio had no greater success with his pupil Favorinus when he attempted to discourage this affectation.50 Audience response and popular demand were the final arbiter in these matters and thus usurped the power to determine the shape of oratory. Dio, Quintilian and Isaeus witness and oppose, but fail to arrest, this trend. Dio's warning to the unruly Alexandrians and their singing philosophers, poets and orators, and even the threat of further political instability in Alexandria, could not stem the tide.51 The leaders do not censure, they all sing.
47See Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 173, n. 56 in which he compares ᾄδω, #22, with ᾠδη in the glossary of rhetorical terms in Philostratus, Lives of the Sophists, LCL, p. 575. Cf. Cicero, Orator, XVIII.57; Lucian, A Professor of Public Speaking, 19; Quintilian, X.3.57; and Dio, Or. 32.68.
48On the contrast between the classical style of the Atticists, who looked back to the diction and composition of literary prose found in Athens in the fifth and fourth centuries B.C., and the Asianists, the more popular form with its reflection of more contemporary Greek style and adaptability in the early empire, see Kennedy, The Art of Rhetoric in the Roman World (Princeton: Princeton University Press, 1972), pp. 241-42.
49LCL translates 'and yet while I knew there are philosophers called Cynics, harpists of the canine breed have been produced here alone'. Better, 'And yet while I knew there were the socalled philosophers' (just described as whining and howling dogs instead of swans and nightingales) 'the singing Cynics are found only here.' The former hardly does justice to text or context.
50Philostratus, Lives of the Sophists, 513, 490, and a brief description in LCL, XXV. Favorinus' Corinthian Oration was included in Dio's Orations, as was his declamation On Fortune, Or. 37.64. On his singing literary style see Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 59, n. 47 and p. 179, n. 1.
51Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 37, where he describes the history of Alexandria under Roman rule as one of continual unrest.
53
In a further explanation of the functions of orators and sophists in Alexandria, #68, Dio refers to two known facts about these professionals. Firstly, the orators' courtroom activity fulfils a well-established role, which is clearly attested elsewhere in Dio and in other literary, as well as non-literary sources.52 Secondly, the sophists in their lecture rooms teach students to declaim,
as documented in P.Oxy. 2190 and in Philostratus.53 Dio refers to the
possibility of having a sophist in one's neighbourhood, suggesting that they were visible in Alexandrian life, #68b. Again he engages in synkrisis between himself and such people in terms of his role, for he is noble, while they are 'flatterers and impostors', # 10-11,68.
Orators and sophists in Dio's corpus
This picture of Alexandrian orators and sophists in Or. 32 is not peculiar to that speech; it occurs also in Dio's Olympian discourse. He there describes them as 'able orators, most charming writers of both verse and prose, and finally, like gorgeous peacocks, sophists in great numbers, men who are lifted aloft as on wings by their fame and disciples', Or. 12.5. He expresses 'Socratic' surprise that his audience deigns to listen to him, 'a man who knows nothing and makes no claim of knowing'. In the city of his birth he denies possessing ability as an orator in the marketplace and in litigation, and hastens to add that he once appeared in court on behalf of a man whose chance of a fair trial was remote. He claims to seek no patronage or pay from anybody. This synkrisis is part of a skilful commendation of his own integrity, especially as he proceeds to hint that his pursuit of the interests of the state led him to neglect his own property, Or. 43.61.
One also sees views of the orators at work in Dio's speeches.54 Some are only concerned with money, 'twisting and warping' unclear laws with eloquence and perverting justice.55 Some 'advise the state' (συμβουλεύειν) and help legislate on its behalf.56 In Tarsus 'the orators' alone were allowed to
52Or. 7.38,39,48,49; 8.9; 18.14; 35.15. For non-literary evidence see, e.g., BGU 15,19,592, 969; P.Flor. 61; P.Lond. 354; P.Mil.Volg. 25; PSI 450; P.Harr. 67; P.Fam.Tebt. 19, 287; P.Ryl. 653; and P.Oxy. 37, 472, 707, 2111 for orators and their speeches. For a peroration capable of 'singing' see, e.g., P.Princ. 119 and P.Vindob.Gr. inv. no. 39757. On the legal profession in Egypt see R. Taubenschlag, 'The Legal Profession in Greco-Roman Egypt', in Festschrift Fritz Schulz (Weimar: Hermann Böhlaus Nachfolger, 1951), vol. II, pp. 188-92.
53Lives of the Sophists, 514,547,604, P.Oxy. 2190.20. See discussion on pp. 31-33.
54 Or. 21.1; 7.38-39; 48.63; 8.9; 34.15; 43.6; 76.4.
55Or. 8.9; 21.1; 76.4.
56Or. 4.108; 13.22-23; 18.14; 21.1-5; 38.5; 43.6.
54
make public speeches, possibly a reference to occasions when an official encomium was required, Or. 34.1. Dio envisages the orator 'in the noble and real sense of the word', but recognises that like their counterparts in court, there are good and bad orators. Some stoop to seek bribes, Or. 22.2-5.
In discussing sophists, Dio notes that some have schools. While some of these do their task well, others fail their students, 'leaving them to grow old in ignorance'. Their flawed approach to paideia robs men of the classical virtues.57 They are mercenary, engaging in rivalry with other sophists; their pupils, out of loyalty, contribute to the factionalism.58
The sophists also have a leadership role in the polis with accompanying social status, and are courted by communities and officials as well as pupils.59 They advise kings though they do not know how to live themselves. Dio states that they are as ineffectual as eunuchs.60 They love their reputation and so never say anything to offend their audience; thus they simply expound the views of their hearers. He parodies the sort of sophist whose liver swelled when praised and shrivelled when censured,61 and complains that they will not debate with him, even claiming that they hate him.62 His attacks on the ancient sophists are also applied to his contemporaries.63
The above views correspond in the main with those expressed in Or. 32 as they portray the movement in various parts of the empire. Indeed, this brief review of Dio's opinion of orators and sophists in his corpus explicates the picture of the movement in Alexandria. One easily gains the impression of a 'blanket condemnation' of sophists, and this may be why the term 'sophist' itself is thought by some to be pejorative. However, Moles demonstrates that this is not the case in Dio, and provides a far more balanced presentation of the evidence than either C. P. Jones or P. Desideri.64 He notes Dio's pains to reas-
57Or. 4.14,28,32,36,38; 35.10.
58Or. 6.21; 8.9; 12.13.
59Or. 6.12; 77/8.27.
60Or. 4.35; 28.35.
61Or. 6.21; 8.33; 12.5; 35.8,81; 55.7; 66.12; 77/8.27.
62Or. 12.3; 47.16.
63Or. 54.1,4.
64For the treatment by Moles see 'Dio on Sophists and Rhetoric", in 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 88-93. Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 9, n. 9 surveys Dio's sophists with only three citations out of over forty references to them in his orations. One of those three is acknowledged by him to be tentative. Nevertheless, upon it he seeks to build a case for the term to describe philosophers who 'teach mere words without thought'. In 'The Reliability of Philostratus', in G. W. Bowersock (ed.), Approaches to the Second Sophistic (University Park, Penn.: American Philological Association, 1974), pp. 11-16, he endorses Bowersock's definition of the sophist, but his treatment of Dio has been coloured by his own work on
55
sure his audience that he is not attacking all sophists:65 'However my remarks are not levelled at all sophists, for there are some who follow that calling honourably and for the good of others, men to whom we should pour libation and offer incense' (Or. 35.10). The term itself, therefore, does not have negative connotations. There are honourable virtuoso orators to contrast with those who are not worthy of the name. In Or. 4.35 Dio can speak of 'so-called sophists', implying that the term is inappropriate to some who claim it because they do not conform to the standards of their profession.66 The phrase 'the most ignorant sophist' leaves open the possibility that some are not ignorant, as Dio observes elsewhere.67 While contemporaries of Dio balked at designating the ancient Seven Sages as 'sophists', Dio did not.68 Or. 71 provides an elaborate synkrisis of philosophers and sophists with Hippias. While that philosopher is certainly superior, Dio notes that this well-known ancient sophist had a high degree of skill in both manual and intellectual pursuits.69 In discussing a case of bribery Dio tells his audience his criticisms are not against the art of rhetoric nor against good exponents but rather against bad ones. Moles maintains that Dio's most revealing comment is found in Or. 19.3ff, where he says, 'whenever I attend a sophist's lecture, on account of an uncontrolled craving which possesses me for the spoken word…and this is the way I have nearly always been affected when listening to sophists and orators'. Moles rightly adds that this is hardly Dio the aggressive philosopher, scourge of all sophists.70 Dio's use of the term 'sophist' thus needs to be reviewed.
Philostratus' evidence where he says it is primarily used of 'inferior' or 'false philosophers'. G. R. Stanton, 'Sophists and Philosophers: Problems of Classification', AJP 94.4 (1973), 351-64, whose primary interest was to weigh Dio's use of the terms 'sophist' and 'philosopher' to determine what he and his contemporaries said of themselves, produced three major categories, namely 'neutral', 'derogatory' and 'abusive or derisive'. P. Desideri clearly demonstrates that Stanton's 'neutral' examples belong to the other categories. Desideri says he knows of only one 'neutral' example of Dio's sophists, the reference to Solon and 'the great many of ancient sophists', Or. 10.26. Of Stanton's examples and other pejorative passages, Desideri, Dione di Prusa, pp. 242-43, suggests that Dio's nuances are simply varying degrees of disgust with the sophist. Stanton does not cite Or. 35.10 as a favourable comment, nor does Desideri note it as an important comment on the existence of 'good' sophists.
65Moles, 'Dio on Sophists and Rhetoric', 91.
66On the discussion of the meaning of 'the so-called' see Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 32, n. 21.
67Or. 55.7; 35.10.
68Or. 10.26; cf. Plutarch, Moralia, 385e.
69Dio here observes the difference between the ancient sophists and those who are his contemporaries.
70. On bribery Or. 22.5; Moles, 'The Career and Conversion of Dio Chrysostom', 92; cf. Desideri, Dione di Prusa, p. 243.
56
Jones suggests that the word is used pejoratively, usually of the philosophers, but tentatively cites only one example, Or. 32.11.71 It needs to be noted, however, that Dio does not use either σοφιστής or σοφιστικός when speaking of philosophers. When he critiques the behaviour of those whom he opposes he refers to 'those who are called philosophers'. Of the seventy occurrences of the term 'philosopher' in his orations, it never appears as a collocation with σοφιστής.72 Had Dio used 'sophist' of charlatan or impostor philosophers, then Or. 34.3 would have provided him with the ideal opportunity to do so. In that discourse the philosophers of Tarsus had been guilty of some misdemeanour. But Dio instead encourages the citizens not to curse all philosophers, for no person is a philosopher who is unjust, wicked, among the Brachmanes, or who harms their country or bands together against their fellow citizens. Just as J. Glucker complains that the later meaning of καθηγητής, namely that of 'professor', has been read back into the earlier period, so too in the case of Dio, our pejorative connotations of 'sophist' have been read into the first-century philosophers.73
Secondly, even Jones hesitates to cite Or. 32.11 in support of his contention that the term is usually used pejoratively of philosophers. There Dio contrasts the dearth of noble, independent souls with the abundance of 'flatterers, impostors and sophists'. Later in the oration he uses these same terms after his encomium, #39, this time while instructing the crowd not to compare him with those who 'habitually sing such strains, whether orators or poets'. His reason is that they are 'clever persons, mighty sophists, wonderworkers' (δεινοὶ ἐκεῖνοι καὶ μεγάλοι σοφισταὶ καὶ γόητες), while in comparison he is 'quite ordinary and prosaic', #39. Why does Dio use these terms κόλαξ and γόης with σοφιστής? They were used of sophists by both Plato and Demosthenes, and in his own lifetime, by Philo, to reflect the bewitching effect they had on audiences.74 Thus 'flatterer' and 'impostor' were used pejoratively of sophists, but the term 'sophist' was not used by Dio to pillory philos-
71Thus apparently Dio, Or. 32.11; Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 162, n. 9.
72It is wrong to argue that the term 'philosopher' here means simply a lover of wisdom. Rather, Dio is arguing that philosophers are meant to be lovers of wisdom in every sense of the
word.
73J. Glucker, Antiochus and the Late Academy, Hypomnemata 56 (Gottingen: Vandenhoeck and Ruprecht, 1978), p. 127; and Jones, Roman World of Dio Chrysostom, p. 9.
74Plato, Symposium, 203d; Demosthenes, De Corona, 276. For subsequent discussionfrom Aristotle onwards see J. de Romilly, Magic and Rhetoric in Ancient Greece (Cambridge, Mass, and London: Harvard University Press, 1975). No reference is made by her to the discussion in Philo, e.g., Her. 302, or A. J. Malherbe (ed.), The Cynic Epistles (Missoula: Scholars Press, 1977), 6.30, although the study examines the evidence of Aristides and Philostratus. For the discussion of this issue in Philo see pp. 88-91.
57
ophers. Or. 32.11 does not support Jones' thesis concerning the identification of sophists with philosophers but instead places them on opposite sides of the scales. The sophists in Dio were a specific group of public orators and poets in Alexandria; hence the term is to be understood in the technical sense of a virtuoso orator with a large public following.75